By Lee Smolin
Allen Lane
Hardback: £20
E-book: £11.99
This is a fascinating and thought-provoking book about the nature of time and its role in explaining the universe. Smolin is an original thinker who is unafraid to challenge established orthodoxy. He argues that modern attempts to understand the universe have reached an impasse as a result of the extraction of time from our concept of reality.
The book is presented in two parts. The first offers an historical and philosophical account of how we have arrived at a timeless view of the world. The second develops ideas for a new approach to physics, which incorporates time as a central and fundamental theme. While both parts are interesting and relevant, physicists might find it more satisfying to read the second part first. There is also an epilogue where Smolin discusses some of the implications of redefining our concept of time and reality and how we might meet the challenges of the future, such as climate change and market economics. Finally, he considers the nature of consciousness.
Smolin begins by illustrating, with the simple example of projectile motion, how time can be excluded from our understanding of a physical system by using mathematical constructs. The role of mathematics is to make a physical system abstract, rendering it eternal and timeless. Here Smolin gives an excellent account of the history of the Copernican Revolution, Johannes Kepler and Galileo Galilei. His unique perspective gives new insight into how each world view might have developed and persisted. At each stage the concept of time becomes increasingly obsolete, culminating in the determinism of the Newtonian paradigm. Relativity is no less deterministic, leading us to a timeless “block universe” picture where reality is the whole history of the universe at once.
In what he calls “doing physics in a box”, Smolin examines the applicability of the Newtonian paradigm to cosmology. A physical system can never be isolated from external influences, so the solutions are an approximation to reality. The approximation can be removed by taking the universe as a whole into consideration but such a step cannot be justified because the Newtonian paradigm necessarily applies to a system that is part of a whole. Smolin calls the inappropriate application of physical laws to the universe a “cosmological fallacy”. His reasoning draws attention to the distinction between physics-in-a-box and cosmology. “The universe is an entity different in kind from any of its parts.”
Smolin is a strong proponent of Leibnitz and the principle of sufficient reason, which states that if there is more than one possibility for things to be as they are, then there must be a sufficient reason for the actual outcome being the case. He uses this to great effect in defining his principles for a new cosmology. In particular, “there should be nothing in the universe that acts on other things without itself being acted upon.” This expresses the philosophy of relationism, where every entity in the universe evolves dynamically, including the physical laws governing the universe. These laws then “become explicable only when they participate in the dance of change and mutual influence that makes the world a whole”. A consequence of relationism, Smolin argues, is that symmetries and conservation laws can only be approximations to reality.
Smolin is keen to emphasize a new approach to a theory of the universe that is not constrained by the Newtonian paradigm. He attempts to provide a framework for a new theory, insisting that it must be able to provide falsifiable predictions. In this sense he is less speculative than those who opt for a multiverse of universes that are not causally connected to our own. He proposes the existence of many universes but with causal connections, which in principle allow their existence to be detected. A possible candidate for the new theory is cosmological natural selection – the subject of his earlier book The Life of the Cosmos – in which universes reproduce through the creation of new universes within black holes. The presence of a large number of black holes in a universe is a measure of its fitness in evolutionary terms. The analogy with Darwinian evolution raises the fascinating possibility of novel outcomes, similar to the emergence of new species through natural selection.
This book is great for providing numerous thought-provoking ideas. The reader does not have to agree with all of them to be stimulated into pondering the nature of time. Unsettling and controversial in places, it offers a much needed re-examination of some of our most cherished views.